Path Algebra for Categories
Solution 1:
- I think (but might be false because I'm not that well-informed when it comes to infinite-dimensional algebras, it is certainly true if you replace $\mathbb{R}$ by an appropriate finite set) that in this case there is no quiver $Q$ such that $R[(\mathbb{R},\leq)]\cong RQ$. Instead you will have that $R[(\mathbb{R},\leq)]\cong RQ/I$, where $Q$ is the quiver with arrows $a\to b$ whenever $a\leq b$ and $I$ is the ideal spanned by all $\alpha-\gamma\beta$, where $\alpha$ is an arrow representing $a\leq c$, $\beta$ is an arrow representing $a\leq b$ and $\gamma$ is an arrow representing $b\leq c$.
In the finite-dimensional world over algebraically-closed fields the path algebras are in fact only the hereditary algebras (i.e. the algebras such that $\operatorname{Ext}^2$ vanishes) up to Morita equivalence. - I think that this should indeed then not be called a path algebra but maybe a path algebra with relations if you don't want to use category ring.
- To give a quiver (with relations) is giving much more information than giving just a category. In some sense the quivers satisfy some minimality assumptions. An example: The number of arrows between two vertices in a given quiver is the $\operatorname{Ext}^1$ between the corresponding simple modules. The $\operatorname{Ext}^2$ describes the number of relations needed in a minimal set of relations on the quiver.
- For your question whether a category algebra is the same as a quiver with relations (I'm only talking about the case of a finite quiver.) That depends on what equivalence relation you are imposing. If you want to use "up to isomorphism" then the answer is "No". For example consider the category $\mathcal{M}_2$ with two isomorphic objects (and no other morphisms except the two isomorphisms and the two identities). Then it is easy to check $k[\mathcal{M}_2]\cong M_2(k)$ (the ring of $2\times 2$-matices over $k$.) This is not isomorphic to any path algebra of a quiver since its module category is semisimple (all representations are finite sums of simple ones) but the only path algebras which are semisimple are $k^n$ (as the quiver take $n$ vertices and no arrows). And these two algebras are never isomorphic. That's why I wrote in 1. that you have to consider them up to Morita equivalence. Two algebras are called Morita equivalent if their module categories are equivalent. By the theorem of Gabriel there is exactly one path algebra in each equivalence class of finite dimensional algebras. This is exactly the basic algebra (meaning that the finite dimensional simple modules are $1$-dimensional).
- One other reason to consider quivers first is maybe educational. It is quite easy to speak about representations of quivers without mentioning a category (although implicitely you are dealing with one). So in principle a second year student can take such a course with only knowledge of linear algebra (and not abstract algebra or category theory).
Solution 2:
That's a trap I used to fall into as well. This is the example that you should always always always keep in mind:
Let $G$ be a finite group, then construct a category with one object, and all arrows correspond to elements of $G$ with composition of arrows being group element multiplication, then the category algebra is a group algebra. This is the reason why people, such as Peter Webb and Markus Linklemann, are interested in category algebras as they are generalisation of group algebras. On the other hand, given a group, it is extremely difficult to construct the corresponding path algebra (basic algebra).
Note the "corresponding path algebra" always exists in the following sense (a result of Gabriel): Let $A$ be a finite dimensional algebra with direct sum decomposition $ A= \bigoplus_{i=1}^n P_i^{\oplus m_i}$ (i.e. $P_i$ are indecomposable projective) and take $M=\bigoplus_{i=1}^n P_i$, then the path algebra $kQ/I$ corresponding to $A$ (constructed using Ext-quiver) is isomorphic to $End_A(M)$.
So to answer your question (1) and (2): Given a path algebra $A=kQ/I$, you can construct a category which capture homological behaviour of $kQ/I$ is simply given by treating $Q$ as a category, and relations of compositions given by $I$. Here each object (=vertex in $Q$) in the category has ONLY ONE invertible endomorphism corresponding to the primitive idempotent of that vertex. In this way you can say category algebra is a generalisation of path algebra.
Concerning to your third question, I can't give a very clear answer, these are what my supervisor told me years ago, so I hope someone can give some supplementary comments: There are various reason that we go from quiver to category. Sometimes because we do not want to deal with the algebra directly. (for example, V. Mazorchuk (and possibly Y. Drozd) is one of the people who uses this approach very often.) A better reason is that "path algebra of an infinite quiver" is (was?) an unclear concept, as you don't have things like Gabriel's theorem/lemma as mentioned above, and you need to deal with certain issues arising from infinite dimensional algebras. On the other hand, there is no obvious obstruction when we look at a category with infinite objects.
So why do we still favour path algebras? The reason is most techniques that work on path algebras do not carry over to category algebras. When you have a path algebra, most homological work becomes combinatorial. Yet if you have a category algebra, it is still very difficult to see what the projective indecomposables are (remember the group algebra!).