Surjectivity implies injectivity and conversely

Let $S$ be a finite set, and $f : S \to S$ a function. Then the following are equivalent:

  • $f$ is injective.
  • $f$ is surjective.
  • $f$ is bijective.

This is really just a counting argument. First, suppose $f$ is injective. If $S$ has $n$ elements, by our assumption, this means the image of $f$ has at least $n$ elements. But the image of $f$ is contained in $S$, so it has at most $n$ elements; so the image of $f$ contains exactly $n$ elements and is therefore the whole of $S$, i.e. $f$ is surjective.

Next, suppose $f$ is surjective. So, for each $y$ in $S$, there is an $x$ in $S$ such that $y = f(x)$; we choose one such $x$ for each $y$ and define a function $g : S \to S$ so that $g(y) = x$. By construction, $f(g(y)) = y$, so $g$ must be injective, and hence, must be surjective by the above argument. So $g$ is a bijection, and $f$ is a left inverse for $g$. But a left inverse for a bijection is also a right inverse, so this implies $f$ is a bijection, and a fortiori an injection.


Notice that the very first part of the argument fails when $S$ is not finite. For example, let us consider the function $f : \mathbb{N} \to \mathbb{N}$ defined by $f(x) = x + 1$. This function is certainly injective but is not surjective. Similarly, the function $g : \mathbb{N} \to \mathbb{N}$ defined by $f(0) = 0$ and $f(x + 1) = x$ is surjective, but not injective.


Suppose that $f$ is an injective function and not surjective, i.e. there is point $y\in S$ such that there is no point $x\in S$ with $f(x)=y$. Since $f$ is a function, every $x\in S$ must work as abscissa in the relation $f$. Hence we must have some $x_1 \ne x_2$ with $f(x_1)=f(x_2)$, which gives a contradiction. Therefore $f$ must be onto.