Why is convexity a requirement for Brouwer fixed points? Shouldn't "no holes" be good enough?
Brouwer's fixed point theorem:
Every continuous function $f$ from a convex compact subset $K$ of a Euclidean space to $K$ itself has a fixed point.
I am wondering why the word "convex" is in there. It seems to me that it is necessary and sufficient for $K$ to have no holes, which is a weaker condition than convexity.
Necessary: if $K$ has a hole, then the continuous mapping that simply rotates points around this hole has no fixed point.
Sufficient: A unit disk in any number of dimensions has a Brouwer fixed point. Any compact, hole-less set $K$ is homeomorphic to the unit disk in some number of dimensions. If we map $K$ to the unit disk $D$ with a homeomorphism $h$, then consider the function from $D$ to $D$ given by $h \circ f \circ h^{-1}$. This is a continuous function from the unit disk to itself (which is convex and compact), so it has a Brouwer fixed point $x$. Then $h(f(h^{-1}(x))) = x$, so $f(h^{-1}(x)) = h^{-1}(x)$, so $h^{-1}(x)$ is a Brouwer fixed point of $K$.
What's wrong with this argument?
Solution 1:
The spirit of your question is correct -- the hypothesis of convexity is unnecessary, and indeed any compact subset of Euclidean space without "holes" has the fixed point property. In particular:
Theorem. Let $K$ be any compact, locally contractible subspace of $\mathbb{R}^n$ whose reduced homology groups are all trivial. Then every continuous map $f\colon K\to K$ has a fixed point.
Here "locally contractible" and "all reduced homology groups are trivial" are a precise formulation of what it means for a space to not have "holes". This theorem was proven by Lefschetz, and it follows from the famous Lefschetz fixed point theorem. Specifically, the Lefschetz fixed point theorem is usually stated only for simplicial complexes, but it is known that every compact, locally contractible subset of $\mathbb{R}^n$ is a retract of a simplicial complex, from which the above theorem follows.
By the way, the reasoning you gave is not correct, because a compact, hole-less set $K$ need not be homeomorphic to a disk. For a simple example, the union of finitely many line segments in $\mathbb{R}^2$ meeting at a point is compact and "hole-less" (in the sense of the theorem above), but is not homeomorphic to a disk in any dimension. The above theorem says that any map from such a space to itself must have a fixed point.
Solution 2:
It is just that a convex compact set is homeomorphic to the unit ball. And the fixed point theorem works for those spaces.