The cardinality of the set of all finite subsets of an infinite set
Let $X$ be an infinite set of cardinality $|X|$, and let $S$ be the set of all finite subsets of $X$. How can we show that Card($S$)$=|X|$? Can anyone help, please?
The cardinality is at least $|X|$, since $S$ contains all singletons.
Let $S_n$ be the subset of $S$ consisting of all subsets of cardinality exactly $n$. Then $S$ is the disjoint union of the $S_n$.
Now, for any positive integer $n$, the number of subsets of $X$ of cardinality $n$ is at most $|X|^n = |X|$ (equality since $|X|$ is infinite); because an $n$-tuple of elements of $X$ determines a subset of $X$ of cardinality at most $n$; and every subset with $n$ elements determines only finitely many distinct $n$-tuples of elements of $X$ (namely, $n!$). So $|S_n|\leq n!|X|^n = |X|$ for all $n$.
Therefore: \begin{align*} |X| &\leq |S| = \left|\bigcup_{n=0}^{\infty} S_n\right| = \sum_{n=0}^{\infty}|S_n|\\ &= \sum_{n=1}^{\infty}|S_n| \leq \sum_{n=1}^{\infty}|X|\\ &= \aleph_0|X| = |X|, \end{align*} with the last equality since $|X|\geq\aleph_0$.
Thus, $|X|\leq |S|\leq |X|$, so $|S|=|X|$.
This is an old post, but because Arturo's otherwise good answer is a bit cavalier on choice usage and the comments don't make the exact level of choice needed entirely clear, I thought I'd explain my own approach to the question in a ZF framework.
We can establish the following with no well-orderability assumptions:
Lemma: If $X$ is a nonempty set and $X\times X\approx X$ (meaning there is a bijection from $X\times X$ to $X$), then $\bigcup_{n\in\omega}X^n\approx\omega\times X$.
Proof: Fix a bijection $f:X\times X\to X$ and $x_0\in X$. Then we can define
$$g_0:x\in X^0\mapsto x_0$$ $$g_{n+1}:x\in X^{n+1}\mapsto f(g_n(x\restriction n), x_n)$$
Then by induction we have that $g_n$ is an injection from $X^n$ to $X$, and then $$h:x\in\bigcup_{n\in\omega}X^n\mapsto \langle \operatorname{dom}x,g_{\operatorname{dom}x}(x)\rangle$$
is an injection from $\bigcup_{n\in\omega}X^n$ to $\omega\times X$. (We use that $X^n$ for different $n$ are disjoint because $x\in X^n$ implies $x:n\to X$ so that $\operatorname{dom}x=n$.) For the reverse inequality, define
$$j:n\in\omega,x\in X\mapsto(z\in n+1\mapsto x).$$
Then if $j(n,x)=j(m,y)$ we have $(z\in n+1\mapsto x)=(z\in m+1\mapsto y)$ so the domains of the functions are equal, i.e. $n+1=m+1\Rightarrow n=m$, and also $x=j(n,x)(0)=j(m,y)(0)=y$.
Adding an assumption of well-ordering allows us to simplify the statement to what we are after:
If $X$ is an infinite well-orderable set, then the set $[X]^{<\omega}$ of finite subsets of $X$ is equipollent to $X$.
Proof: Since singletons are in $[X]^{<\omega}$ and naturally bijective with $X$, $X\preceq[X]^{<\omega}$. For the converse, we have $X\times X\approx X$ because $X$ is infinite well-orderable, so by the lemma $$\bigcup_{n\in\omega}X^n\approx\omega\times X\preceq X\times X\approx X;$$ thus $\bigcup_{n\in\omega}X^n$ is also well-orderable, so we can reverse the surjection $f:\bigcup_{n\in\omega}X^n\to[X]^{<\omega}$ which maps each function to its range to get an injection. Thus, $X\preceq [X]^{<\omega}\preceq\bigcup_{n\in\omega}X^n\preceq X$.