Clarification of McKay's Proof of Cauchy's Theorem for Groups

Below is a presentation that I devised to clarify McKay's proof (from an old sci.math post).

Lemma $\ $ If $g$ is an element of a group and $p$ is prime then $g^p = 1\:\Rightarrow\:$ $g$ has order $p$ or $1$.

Proof $\ $ If $g$ has order $n$ then $g^n = g^p = 1 \Rightarrow\ g^{(n,p)} = 1.$ But $(n,p) = p$ or $1$ by $p$ prime.

Theorem $\ $ Suppose that $p$ is prime, $G$ is a finite group of order $n,$ and $R =$ #$p$'th roots of $1$ in $G,$ i.e. $\: R = \#\{ g \in G :\ g^p = 1 \}.\:$ Then

$$ R \equiv n^{p-1}\ ({\rm mod}\ p),\ \ {\rm and}\ \ R > 1 \iff p\mid n$$

Proof $\ $ Let $S$ be the set of all $p$-tuples of elements from $G$ whose product is $1,$ i.e.

$$ S = \{ (g_1,g_2,\ldots,g_p) :\ g_1 g_2\cdots g_p = 1,\ g_i \in G \}$$

Let $F$ be the cyclic rotation on $p$-tuples

$$ F(\color{#C00}{g_1},g_2,\ldots,g_p) = (g_2,g_3,\ldots,g_p,\color{#C00}{g_1}) $$

Clearly $F^p = 1,$ so $F$ is a permutation on $S.$ Recall that a permutation $F$ decomposes into disjoint cycles (orbits) $\:\langle F\rangle s = \{F^k s :\, k \in \Bbb Z\},$ the classes of the equivalence relation $s \sim t \!\iff\! s = F^k t,$ for some $k \in \Bbb Z.$ Thus the cycles of $F$ form a partition $S = \langle F\rangle s_1 \cup \cdots \cup \langle F\rangle s_m.$

Consider the permutation $F$ restricted to some cycle $C.$ Notice the order of $F$ on $C$ is the cycle length $n$ of $C.$ But since $F^p = 1,$ the lemma implies that $n = p$ or $1.$ So $S$ decomposes into disjoint cycles of length $p$ or $1,$ yielding one count for $|S|$. For another, notice $S$ has $n^{p-1}$ elements since, after freely choosing the first $p-1$ elements of a $p$-tuple in $S,$ the last element must be the inverse of the product of the others. Comparing both counts

$$ |S| = n^{p-1}\! =\, Q\,p + R,\ \ \ Q = \#p{\rm\!-\!cycles,}\ \ R = \#1{\rm\!-\!cycles} $$

A $\:1$-cycle has $Fs = s,$ so $s$ has all entries identical, say $g,$ so $g^p = 1,$ i.e. $g$ is a $p$'th root of $1$ in $G$ iff $g$ is a $1$-cycle of $R.$ Hence mod $p: n^{p-1} = R,$ the number of $p$'th roots of $1$ in $G.$ If $p\mid n$ then $p\mid R.$ But $R > 0$ since always $1^p = 1,$ hence $R \ge p > 1.$ Conversely, if $R > 1$ then $G$ has $g \ne 1$ with $g^p = 1,$ so the lemma implies $g$ has order $p.$ But also $g^n = 1,$ so $p\mid n.\ \ $ QED

Corollary 1 $\ $ (Cauchy's Theorem) $\ $ If a group $G$ has order $n$ divisible by a prime $p$ then $G$ has a subgroup of order $p.$

Proof $\ \ p\mid n\:$ so the theorem implies $R > 1,$ i.e. $G$ has a $g \ne 1$ with $g^p = 1.$ The lemma implies that $g$ has order $p,$ so $g$ generates a cyclic subgroup $\langle g\rangle$ of order $p.$

Corollary 2 $\ $ (F$\ell$T: Fermat's $\ell$ittle Theorem) $\ $ If $p$ is prime and $p\nmid n$ then $n^{p-1} \equiv 1 \pmod p.$

Proof $\ $ Apply the theorem to any (e.g. cyclic) group of order $n.$

Corollary 3 $\ \ $ Theorem $\Rightarrow$ Lemma

Proof $\ $ Suppose $g^p = 1,\ g \ne 1.$ Let $n$ be the order of $g.$ Apply the theorem to the cyclic group $\langle g\rangle$ generated by $g.$ Note $g^p = 1^p = 1\:\Rightarrow\: R > 1,$ so $p\mid n,$ therefore $n = p.$


I think I see it: if we have $\,(x_1,x_2,...,x_p)\,$ , with $\,x_i\neq x_j\,$ for some $\,1\leq i\neq j\leq p\,$, then all the elements

$$(x_1,x_2,...,x_p)\,,\,(x_2,x_3,...,x_p,x_1)\,...,(x_p,x_1,x_2,...,x_{p-1})$$

are different, and that's what McKay means in his paper.

The version I know goes like follows:

Let

$$\,S:=\{(x_1,...,x_p)\in G^p\;\;;\;\;x_1\cdot...\cdot x_p=1\,\,,\,\lnot\forall\,i\,,\,x_i=1\}$$

We get at once that $\,|S|=|G|^{p-1}-1\,$ , and now we define an action of the cyclic group of order $\,p\,\,,\,C_p=\langle\,z\,\rangle\,$ on $\,S\,$ by

$$\,z^k(x_1,...,x_p):=(x_{k+1},x_{k+2},...,x_p,x_1,...,x_k)$$

and, of course, taking the powers (and thus the action) above modulo $\,p\,$.

For any element $\,\bf {x} \in S\,$ ,we get

$$|\mathcal Orb(\bf x)|=[C_p:Stab(x)]$$

Since the right hand number above is either $\,1\,\,\,or\,\,p\,$ but $\,p\nmid |S|\,$ , there must be an element in $\,S\,$ whose orbit has size $\,1\,$, and this means

$$\exists\,(x_1,...,x_p)\in S\;\;s.t.\;\;x_1=x_2=...=x_p\Longrightarrow x^p=1$$

and since $\,x_i\neq 1\,$ we're done.


@Carl, from the proof of DonAntonio you get as a nice bonus that $\#\{g\in G : order(g)=p\} \equiv -1$ mod $p$. Can you see that?